研究生: |
杜鎮宇 Tu, Cheng-Yu |
---|---|
論文名稱: |
Respect for Persons and Education: A Study of R. S. Peters' Idea of Respect and Its Implication for Education Respect for Persons and Education: A Study of R. S. Peters' Idea of Respect and Its Implication for Education |
指導教授: |
林建福
Lin, Chien-Fu |
口試委員: |
張鍠焜
Chang, Huang-Kun 陳伊琳 Chen, Yi-Lin 林建福 Lin, Chien-Fu |
口試日期: | 2024/01/29 |
學位類別: |
碩士 Master |
系所名稱: |
教育學系 Department of Education |
論文出版年: | 2024 |
畢業學年度: | 112 |
語文別: | 英文 |
論文頁數: | 208 |
中文關鍵詞: | 尊重 、表面尊重 、皮德思 、轉變 、道德反思 、積極容忍 、肯認 |
英文關鍵詞: | Respect, Ostensible Respect, R. S. Peters, Transformation, Moral Reflection, Positive Tolerance, Recognition |
研究方法: | 敘事分析 、 內容分析法 |
DOI URL: | http://doi.org/10.6345/NTNU202400366 |
論文種類: | 學術論文 |
相關次數: | 點閱:112 下載:16 |
分享至: |
查詢本校圖書館目錄 查詢臺灣博碩士論文知識加值系統 勘誤回報 |
彼此尊重已經是當代社會中不可缺少的價值信念,因此在當代教育裡,從小我們就被教導要尊重別人,以及尊重在倫理生活中的重要性。然而,當我們試圖從記憶中回想自己是如何學習尊重時,卻宛如從睡醒中想辦法憶起熟睡時的甜美夢境般艱難。同樣的,當詢問教育工作者怎麼尊重學生時,他們的回應往往是眼神中流露出肯定尊重的重要性,表達卻像是在水中說話,說了許多嚴肅的話,但聽者或旁觀者只能看見一圈一圈的泡泡。更令人憂心的是,尊重這個價值信念在教育現場變得過度嚴肅和僵化,導致一種“表面尊重”的出現。為了嚴守尊重不同想法的律則,教師往往認為在面對擁有極為不同想法的學生和家長時,因為要尊重他們所以應該盡量保持沉默避免過多干預。坦白的說,就是以視而不見來息事寧人。這些怪象研究者歸結為在不清楚尊重意涵,但又因為尊重是倫理生活極為重要的價值下,展開行動後的結果。本研究將試圖透過探討和延伸皮德思尊重人的想法和其在教育上的應用,來提出一些建議。
在尊重的理論解釋上,本研究主張尊重人除了依循皮德思說的尊重他人的觀點想法之外,還要包含尊重他人的轉變,以及有轉變的可能性。因此,一位教師若真正尊重學生,他將不只尊重學生當下的觀點想法,還會很慎重的回應,因為假設教師尊重人有轉變和有轉變的可能性,他就會深知他的回應與學生的轉變有密切關聯。所以,即便學生與教師有極為不同的觀點想法,教師仍然有必要慎重且積極的回應學生。奠基在這樣的想法,本研究進一步提供教師三種方式來尊重學生和與自己想法極為不同的學生:一、教師可以經由道德反思的練習來減少對自己的自愛和抑制自己的自傲;二、面對與自己想法極為不同的學生時,教師可以經由道德反思在行動中對學生展現積極容忍;三、在面對每位學生時,教師可以站在能讓學生在未來成為自主的人的觀點來肯認學生。
Respect for one another has become an indispensable value in contemporary society, and this ethos is instilled in individuals from an early age within the framework of contemporary education. However, reflecting on the process through which we acquire an understanding of respect proves to be as challenging as recalling a pleasant dream upon waking. Similarly, when inquiring how educators respect students, their responses often affirm the significance of respect with a gaze that implies its importance, yet their articulations seem to be speaking underwater—uttering serious words, but listeners or observers only perceive concentric circles of bubbles. A more disconcerting observation is the emergence of a phenomenon labeled “ostensible respect” within educational settings. In a bid to strictly adhere to the principle of respecting diverse perspectives, teachers often opt for silence and minimal intervention when confronted with students and parents holding markedly different views. This strategic approach, when candidly described, may be interpreted as a deliberate effort to turn a blind eye to forestall potential disturbances. I attribute these anomalies to the consequences of acting under the pressure to recognize the importance of respecting others in ethical life, coupled with a lack of clarity regarding the nuanced meaning of respect. Therefore, this study endeavors to provide insightful suggestions by delving into and extending R. S. Peters’ idea of respect and its application in education.
Concerning the theoretical meaning of respect, I contend that respecting others extends beyond adhering to what Peters posits, i.e., respecting others’ assertive points of view. Respecting others should also encompass respecting others’ transformations and the potential for transforming. Therefore, if a teacher genuinely respects her students, she will not only respect their current assertive points of view but will also seriously respond to them. The reason is that if a teacher respects the potential for transformation and transformation itself in individuals, she will be acutely aware of the close connection between her responses and the students’ transformations. Consequently, even in situations where students and teachers hold vastly different perspectives, it remains essential for the teacher to respond seriously and actively to the students. Grounded in this perspective, the study further offers three approaches for teachers to respect students: 1. when facing students, teachers should try to reduce their self-love and restrain their self-conceit through the practice of moral reflection; 2. when confronted with students whose perspectives markedly differ from their own, teachers can try to demonstrate positive tolerance through moral reflection in their actions; 3. in interactions with each student, teachers can try to show recognition from the standpoint of allowing pupils to become moral and autonomous agents in the future.
李明輝。(2022)。康德哲學中的Menschheit及其文化哲學意涵。清華學報,52(2),215-248。[Lee, M. H. (2021). “Menschheit” in the Philosophy of Kant and Its Meaning for Cultural Philosophy. Tsing Hua Journal of Chinese Studies, 52(2), 215-248.] DOI: 10.6503/THJCS.202206_52(2).0001
史次耘。(2009)。孟子今註今譯。臺灣商務出版。
教育基本法。(2013)。https://law.moj.gov.tw
Allais, L. (2015). Manifest Reality. Oxford University Press.
Allison, H. E. (2004). Kant's Transcendental Idealism. Yale University Press.
Allison, H. E. (2011). Kant's Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals: A Commentary. Cambridge University Press.
Arcilla, R. V. (1995). For the Love of Perfection: Richard Rorty and Liberal Education. Routledge.
Aristotle. (2009). Nicomachean Ethics (W. D. Ross Trans.). Oxford University Press.
Bakhurst, D. (2011). The Formation of Reason. Wiley Blackwell.
Bakhurst, D. (2012). Freedom and Second Nature in The Formation of Reason. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 19, 172-189. DOI: 10.1080/10749039.2011.64993
Bakhurst, D. (2015). Training, Transformation, and Education. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 76, 301-327. DOI:10.1017/S135824611500003X
Bakhurst, D. (2021). Human nature, reason, and morality. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 55, 1029-1044. DOI:10.1111/1467-9752.12693
Baron, M. W. (1995). Kantian Ethics Almost Without Apology. Cornell University Press.
Biesta, G. J. J. (2016). The Beautiful Risk of Education. Paradigm.
Biesta, G. J. J. (2021). The three gifts of teaching: Towards a non-egological future for moral education. Journal of Moral Education, 50 (1), 39-54. DOI: 10.1080/03057240.2020.1763279
Benn S. I. & Peters R. S. (1959). Social Principles and The Democratic State. George Allen & Unwin Ltd.
Blackburn, S. (2008). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (2 editions). Oxford University Press.
Bonnett, M. (1986). Personal Authenticity and Public Standards. In David E. Cooper (Ed.), Education, values, and mind: Essays for R. S. Peters (pp.111-133). Routledge.
Bonnett, M. (2021). Environmental, Consciousness, Nature and The Philosophy of Education. Routledge
Bowers, C. A. (2018). Ideological, Cultural, and Linguistic Roots of Educational Reforms to Address the Ecological Crisis: The Selected Works of C. A. (Chet) Bowers. Routledge.
Cavell, S. (1976). Must We Mean What We Say? Cambridge University Press.
Cavell, S. (1988). Themes Out of School: Effects and Causes. Chicago University Press.
Cheng, T. (2021). John McDowell on Worldly Subjectivity: Oxford Kantian Meets Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences. Bloomsbury Academic.
Cooke, M. (2006). Re-Presenting the Good Society. MIT Press.
Cuypers, S. E. (2013). R. S. Peters. Bloomsbury.
Darwall, S. (1977). Two kinds of respect. Ethics, 88(1), 36-49. DOI:10.1086/292054.
Darwall, S. (2004). Respect and the Second-Person Standpoint. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 78(2), 43–59. DOI: 10.2307/3219724
Darwall, S. (2008). Kant on Respect, Dignity, and the Duty of Respect. In M. Betzler (Ed.), Kant's Ethics of Virtue (pp. 175-200). De Gruyter.
Darwall, S. (2009). The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Harvard University Press.
Derry, J. (2008). Technology-enhanced learning: A question of knowledge. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 42, 505-519. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9752.2008.00638.x
Derry, J. (2016). From Disembodied Intellect to Cultivated Rationality. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 50 (1), 117-122. DOI: 10.1111/1467-9752.12177
Dewey, J. (1934/2005). Art as an Experience. Perigee
DeWitt, J. (2013). Respect for the moral law: The emotional side of reason. Philosophy, 89(1), 31–62. DOI:10.1017/s0031819113000648
Downie, R. S. & Telfer, E. (1969). Respect for persons a Philosophical Analysis of the Moral, Political and Religious Idea of the Supreme Worth of the Individual Person. Routledge.
Downie, R. S., Loudfoot E M. & Telfer, E. (1974). Education and Personal Relationships: A Philosophical Study. Harper & Row.
Emerson, R. W. (1909). The Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson: Vol. 10. Lectures and Biographical Sketches. Fireside Edition.
Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. The Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5-20. DOI: 10.2307/2024717
Gaus, G. (2021). Respect for persons and Public Justification. In Oliver Sensen & Richard Dean (Eds.), Respect: Philosophical Essays (pp. 55-76). Oxford University Press.
Giesinger, J. (2012a). Kant on Dignity and Education. Educational Theory, 62(6), 609-620. https://doi.org/10.1111/edth.12000.x
Giesinger, J. (2012b). Respect in Education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 46(1), 100-112. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9752.2011.00836.x
Guyer, P. (2002). Kant's Deductions of the Principles of Right. In Mark Timmons (Ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretative Essays (pp. 23-64). Oxford University.
Guyer, P. (2016). Kant on Moral Feelings: From the Lectures to the Metaphysics of Morals. In Paul Guyer (Ed.), The Virtues of Freedom: Selected Essays on Kant (pp. 235-259). Oxford University.
Hanh, T. N. (2007). Living Buddha, Living Christ. Riverhead Books.
Hinchliffe, G. (2018). Education, knowledge, and freedom. Philosophy, 93 (2), 211-230. DOI: 10.1017/s0031819117000511
Hirst, P. H. (1965). Liberal Education and The Nature of Knowledge. In R. S. Peters (Ed.), The Philosophy of Education (pp. 87-111). Oxford University Press.
Hirst, P. H. & Peters, R. S. (1970). The Logic of Education. Routledge.
Hirst, P. H. (1974/2013). Knowledge and The Curriculum: A Collection of Philosophical Papers. Routledge.
Hirst, P. H. (1986). Richard Peters' Contribution to the Philosophy of Education. In D. E. Cooper (Ed.) Education, Values and Mind. Essays for R. S. Peters (pp. 8-40). Routledge.
Honneth, A. (1996). The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts (J. Anderson, Trans.). Polity Press.
Honneth, A. (2007). Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory. Polity Press
Honneth, A. (2014a). Freedom's Right: The Social Foundations of Democratic Life. Polity Press.
Honneth, A. (2014b). The normativity of ethical life (F. Koch, Trans.). Philosophy and Social Criticism, 40 (8), 817-826. DOI: 10.1177/0191453714541538
Honneth, A. (2021). Recognition: A Chapter in the History of European Ideas (J. Ganahl, Trans.). Cambridge University Press.
Johnson R. N. (2010). Duties to and regarding others. In Denis Lara (Ed.), Metaphysics of Morals: A Critical Guide (pp.192-209). Cambridge University Press.
Jones, P. H. (2010). Toleration and Recognition: What Should We Teach? In Mitja Sardoč (Ed.), Toleration, Respect and Recognition in Education (pp.33-51). Wiley-Blackwell.
Kant, I. (2001). Religion and Rational Theology (A W. Wood Trans.). Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2002). Critique of Practical Reason (W S. Pluhar Trans.). Hackett.
Kant, I. (2007). Critique of Pure Reason (N K. Smith Trans.). Palgrave.
Kant, I. (2017). The Metaphysics of Morals (M. Gregor Trans.) Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2018). Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (A W. Wood Trans.). Yale University Press.
Kauppine, A. (2014). Moral Sentimentalism. Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Kitcher, P. (2004). Kant's Argument for the Categorical Imperative. Nous, 38 (4), 555-584. DOI: 10.1111/j.0029-4624.2004.00484.x
Kolomý, V. (2023). Kant on Moral Feeling and Respect. Kantian Review, 28(1), 105-123. DOI:10.1017/S1369415422000504
Korsgaard, C., & O'Neill, O. (1996). The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI:10.1017/CBO9780511554476
Lægaard, S. (2010). Recognition and Toleration: Conflicting approaches to diversity in education? In Mitja Sardoč (Ed.), Toleration, Respect and Recognition in Education (pp.17-32). Wiley-Blackwell.
Luntley, M. (2008). Conceptual Development and the Paradox of Learning. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 42 (1), 1-14. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9752.2008.00606.x
Luntley, M. (2011). On Education and Initiation. In Stefaan E. Cuyper & Christopher Martin (Eds.), Reading R. S. Peters Today: Analysis, Ethics and the Aims of Education (pp.38-53). Wiley-Blackwell.
Martin, J. R. (1981). The Ideal of the Educated Person. Educational Theory, 31 (2), 97-109.
Martin, J. R. (2020). The Path Not Taken. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 54 (3), 744-756. DOI: 10.1111/1467-9752.12443
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and World. Harvard University Press.
McDowell, J. (1998). Two sorts of naturalism. In John McDowell, Mind, Value & Reality (pp. 167-197). Harvard University Press.
Misawa, K. (2013). Education as the Cultivation of Second Nature: Two Senses of the Given. Educational Theory, 63 (1), 35-50. DOI: 10.1111/edth.12008
Misawa, K. (2014). Nature, Nurture, Second Nature: Broadening horizons of the philosophy of education. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 46 (5), 499-511. DOI: 10.1080/00131857.2012.762504
Misawa, K. (2020). Nature in Our Experience: Bonnett, McDowell and the Possibility of a Philosophical Study of Human Nature. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 39, 135-150. DOI: 10.1007/s11217-019-09700-0
Montefiore, A. (1986). Prudence and respect for persons: Peters and Kant. In David E. Cooper (Ed.), Education, values and mind: Essays for R. S. Peters (pp.134-148). Routledge.
Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford University Press.
Nguyen, Thi. (2022). The Seductions of Clarity. In Julian Baggini (Ed.), How Do We Know? The Social Dimension of Knowledge (pp. 227-255). Cambridge University Press.
O'Neill, O. (1990). Reason and autonomy in Grundlegung III. In Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (pp. 51-65). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
O’Neil, O. (2002). Instituting Principles: Between Duty and Action. In Mark Timmons (Ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals Interpretative Essays (pp. 331-347). Oxford University Press.
Ovid. (1995). The Metamorphoses of Ovid (M. Allen, Trans.). Mariner Books
Paton, H. J. (1963). The Categorical Imperative: A Study in Kant’s Moral Philosophy. Hutchison of London.
Peters, R. S. (1959/2015). Must an educator have an aim? In R. S. Peters, Authority, Responsibility, and Education (pp.122-131). Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1964). The place of philosophy in the training of teachers. In R. S. Peters, Education and the Education of Teachers (pp.135-150). Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1966a/2020). Ethics and Education. Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1966b). The Philosophy of Education. In J. W. Tibble (Ed.), The Study of Education. Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1967/2010). What is an educational process? In R. S. Peters (Eds.), The Concept of Education (pp. 1-16). Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1970). Education and the educated man. In R. S. Peters, Education and the Education of Teacher (pp. 3-21). Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1971). Reason and Passion. In R. S. Peters, Psychology and Ethical Development: A Collection of Articles on Psychological Theories, Ethical Development and Human Understanding (pp. 151-173). George Allen & Unwin.
Peters, R. S. (1972). Education and human development. In R. F. Dearden, P. H. Hirst, and R. S. Peters (Eds.) Education and Reason (pp. 111-130). Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1973a). Freedom and the Development of the Free Man. In P. H. Hirst & P. White (Eds), Philosophy of Education. Major Themes in the Analytic Tradition Volume II: Education and Human Being (pp. 11-31). Routledge.
Peters, R. S. (1973b). The justification of education. In R. S. Peters (Ed.), The Philosophy of Education (pp.239-267). Oxford University Press.
Peters, R. S. (1973c). Reason, Passion, and Levels of Life. In R. S. Peters, Reason and Compassion (pp. 73-102). RKP.
Peters, R. S. (1974a). The Development of Reason. In R. S. Peters, Psychology and Ethical Development: A Collection of Articles on Psychological Theories, Ethical Development and Human Understanding (pp. 119-150). George Allen & Unwin.
Peters, R. S. (1974b). Personal Understanding and Personal Relationships. In R. S. Peters, Psychology and Ethical Development: A Collection of Articles on Psychological Theories, Ethical Development and Human Understanding (pp. 389-412). George Allen & Unwin.
Peters, R. S. (1974c). Subjectivity and Standards. In R. S. Peters, Psychology and Ethical Development: A Collection of Articles on Psychological Theories, Ethical Development and Human Understanding (pp. 413-432). George Allen & Unwin.
Peters, R. S. (1974d). Moral Development and Moral Learning. In R. S. Peters, Psychology and Ethical Development: A Collection of Articles on Psychological Theories, Ethical Development and Human Understanding (pp. 360-385). George Allen & Unwin.
Peters, R. S. (1978). Education as Initiation. In R. S. Peters (Ed). Authority, Responsibility, and Education (pp. 81-107). Routledge.
Peter, R. S. (1979). Democratic Values and Educational Aims. In R. S. Peters, Essays on Educators. George Allen & Unwin.
Peters, R. S. (1983). Philosophy of Education. In Paul Hirst (Ed.), Educational Theory and its Foundation Disciplines (pp. 30-61). Routledge.
Quine, W. V. O. (1961). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20-43. DOI:10.2307/2266637
Rawls, J. (2000). Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy. Harvard University Press.
Reath, A. (2006). Agency and Autonomy in Kant's Moral Theory: Selected Essays. Oxford University Press.
Rorty, R. (2018). Philosophy and The Mirror of Nature. Princeton University Press.
Ryle, G. (1967/2010). Teaching and Training. In R. S. Peters (Ed.), The Concept of Education (pp. 73-82). Routledge.
Schilling, M. (1986). Knowledge and Liberal Education: A Critique of Paul Hirst. Curriculum Studies, 18 (1), 1-16.
Schwarz, L. (2021). Species Egalitarian and Respect for Nature. In Oliver Sensen & Richard Dean (Eds.), Respect: Philosophical Essays (pp. 208-302). Oxford University Press.
Seidler J. V. (1986). Kant, Respect and Injustice: The Limits of Liberal Moral Theory. Routledge.
Sellars, W. (1963). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. In Wilfred Sellars, Science, Perception and Reality (pp. 127-196). Routledge.
Sensen, O. (2011). Kant on Human Dignity. De Gruyter.
Sensen, O. (2017). Dignity: Kant's Revolutionary Conception. In Remy D. (Ed.), Dignity: A History (pp. 237-262). Oxford University Press.
Shakespeare, W. (2015). Hamlet. Penguin Classic.
Siegel, H. (2017). Education's Epistemology: Rationality, Diversity, and Critical Thinking. Oxford University Press.
Singer, P. (2002). One World: The Ethics of Globalization. Yale University Press.
Spiecker, B. (1999). Habituation and Training in Early Moral Upbringing. In Carr, D. & Steutel, J. W. (Eds.), Virtue Theory and Moral Education (pp. 210-223). Routledge.
Stojanov, K. (2011). Overcoming Social Pathologies in Education: On the Concept of Respect in R. S. Peters and Axel Honneth. In Stefaan E. Cuyper & Christopher Martin (Eds.), Reading R. S. Peters Today: Analysis, Ethics and the Aims of Education (pp.156-167). Wiley-Blackwell.
Strawson, P. (1961). Social Morality and Individual Ideal. Philosophy, 36(136), 1–17. DOI: 10.1017/s003181910005779x
Thornton, T. (2019). John McDowell (2nd ed.). Routledge.
Trampota, A. (2021). Kants Konzeption der Tugend als Habitus der Freiheit. Nomos.
Warnock, M. (1986). The Education of the Emotions. In Cooper, D. E. (Ed.), Education, values, and mind, (pp. 172-187). RKP.
White, J. (1984). The Education of the Emotions. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 18 (2), 233-244. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9752.1984.tb00064.x
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical Investigation (G.E.M. Anscombe Trans.) Blackwell.
Wood, A. W. (1991). Unsociable Sociability: The Anthropological Basis of Kantian Ethics. Philosophical Topics, 19(1), 325–351. DOI: 10.5840/philtopics199119122
Wood, A. W. (1999). Kant's Ethical Thought. Cambridge University Press.
Wood, A. W. (2008). Kantian Ethics. Cambridge University Press.